JOHN P. McLAUGHLIN
In this course, we will try to understand the human need to produce and experience art by using the strategies and tools of scientific psychology. We will look at empirical research on our perception and responses to art and the theories such research has generated. Since we cannot do justice to the whole field, we will focus primarily on visual art.
Major categories of research are attempts to (a) isolate the features of
paintings that make them attractive, (b) understand how features of the
anatomy and physiology of the nervous system influence what we like and
do not like and (c) understand the role of cognitive processes in
artistic activity. We will consider theories from perception and from
cognition relevant to understanding, remembering and liking. We shall
also examine some apparent determinants of creativity and identify
dimensions of personality and development that influence aesthetic
responses and artistic activity.
Throughout the centuries, philosophers and critics have thought about
art and have produced a multitude of assertions and pronouncements about
the nature of art or criteria for good art. Unfortunately, there appears
to have been little agreement among these thinkers. Berlyne (1971) argued
that a basic problem in such study was a failure to
distinguish between untestable assertions, which he called normative
assertions, and factual questions, which were testable.
Thus a statement such as, "Truth is beauty" may follow from some
philosophical position, but it does not easily lead to empirically
testable propositions. Factual questions, on the other hand, can be
tested. For example, one can readily design experiments to
examine whether color is a powerful
determinant of aesthetic pleasure.
The point of Berlyne's distinctions was not to denigrate
philosophical speculation, but to call attention to the opportunity
offered by the scientific method. Philosophers have grappled with human
problems of far greater complexity than our science has been able to
address, so far. What was frustrating to scholars such as Berlyne was
that the speculative method has not yielded answers that warrant
universal agreement. Thinking based on the scientific method at least
offers such a possibility.
Definitions
Since definitions shape understanding and guide research,
consideration of the meanings of terms becomes important. Some
difficulties will become apparent when clear definitions are
sought.
Aesthetics
Aesthetic responses are complex responses to external stimuli or to
memories. These responses can include some emotional component, a
cognitive component, an interest component and some other
component, such as awareness of or reflection on that interest or
that emotion.
The emotional component need not be positive, although that is what
people first think of. Aristotle suggested that the role of drama
was to provide us an opportunity to experience negative feelings in
a safe and socially-acceptable way. The appeal of horror movies
needs to be understood this way, I think. In addition to the
feelings of fright or horror produced by such a movie or by a Greek
tragedy, the audience members experience a positive feeling,
perhaps one of relief, or perhaps appreciation of the dramatist's
skill in the creation of emotion
in the audience.
The example of horror movies raises another issue. In most
circumstances, the intensity of the emotional component of an
aesthetic response is lower or weaker than one might experience in
a real-life, emotion-provoking event. Viewing Goya's The 3rd of
May, 1808 (click to see) in the Prado is likely to elicit a degree of revulsion
at murder and political repression and of admiration for indomitable
spirit, but it is not the same as being there. Moreover, the positive
feeling one experiences from this painting, derived from the formal
composition of the pattern as well as the semantic content, would
rarely be classified as intense. This may be due to differences in
the media, e.g., drama is extended over time, but the experience of
a painting need not be.
The cognitive component may be formed by many contributors. In
representational paintings, the artist has included information
about objects, i.e., semantic information. Understanding that
information may be crucial to understanding what the artist was
about and also may be an important determinant of the emotional
component of the aesthetic response. For example, Manet painted
The Execution of the Emperor Maximilian as a protest to the French
government's decision to withdraw support from Maximilian, whom it
had installed on the throne of Mexico, thus abandoning him to his fate.
If you did not know the history, the painting would lose a good bit
of its impact. Another example of this is the use of cultural
symbols to communicate meaning, e.g., a lamb for innocence or for
sacrifice, the goddess Athena or an owl for wisdom and a bull for
power or menace.
Another type of cognitive component is often elicited by more
contemporary works. Nonrepresentational paintings, i.e., paintings
without any semantic content, and some representationals, e.g.,
cubist works, can elicit a sense of bewilderment in the naive
observer. It is unclear what the painting is "about". Even for
sophisticated viewers, some of the high-analytic cubist paintings
by Picasso and by Braque are very difficult to decode. The
painting, in other words, can present a problem that needs solution
and the observer may spend a great deal of time doing the detective
work required to analyze the
visual pattern.
This leads to a consideration of the interest component. The
cubist painting may elicit curiosity which, in turn, prompts the
detective work. There may not be any other emotional or cognitive
component. It is in this sense that interest may be a separate
component in a response. It is also possible, certainly, for
interest in a painting to be the result of a prior emotional or
cognitive response. The realization that a painting portrays some
favorite person or that its pattern capitalizes on some visual
illusion may make the painting
very interesting to the observer.
What is a work of art ?
If you consider the definition of aesthetic response above, the
answer to this question may be seen as relatively straightforward.
We could define a work of art as anything which elicited an
aesthetic response. However, consider the idea more carefully.
Can some object commonly classified as a work of art, such as a
painting or a symphony, elicit an aesthetic response ? Certainly.
Can it fail to elicit the response ? Certainly. A particular
painting might elicit a rich pattern of emotional and cognitive
reactions in one viewer and go virtually unnoticed by another who
is unschooled or too preoccupied. In other words, a "work of art"
may not always evoke an aesthetic
response.
It is also obvious that objects or events that are not commonly
classified as works of art also may reliably elicit aesthetic
responses. Have you seen a sunset or heard waves crashing on a
shore lately ? Your responses to these events can include all of
the components of an aesthetic response. Similarly, a common tool
may evoke conscious positive or negative feelings because of its
appearance or because its design is perfectly suited to the task
and to the user. It is possible, I suppose, to distinguish between
nature and art on the basis of reliablity. This morning, the
forest around my house was wonderfully mysterious in the early fog,
but I will not easily revisit it or recreate the experience because
the fog has now burned off. Goya's painting, on the other hand, I
can visit and revisit as often as I wish (and can afford the air
fare to Madrid). The realization of that distinction may be the subtle
difference between the experiences
of art and nature.
It is clear that a work of art cannot be defined simply by its
effect on observers because it will not have an effect on each and
every observer. Even if we restrict ourselves to a consideration
of objects created by humans, a definition of a work of art cannot
be based on effects, but will have to be found in the
characteristics of the object or in the behavior or intention
of the human who created it or, perhaps most importantly, in its
arbitrary categorization by the
culture.
Let us pursue the idea that a work of art has defining attributes.
One could consider a virtually endless list of characteristics that
an object might have that would distinguish a work of art from
nonart without finding universal agreement among observers.
Fortunately, one does not have to go far down that list before
realizing that there is no simple set of characteristics that does
the job. As Trudy the bag lady put it, referring to her space
chums,"...They find it hard to grasp some things that come easy to
us, because they simply don't have our frame of reference. I show
'em this can of Campbell's tomato soup. I say, 'This is soup.'
Then I show 'em a picture of Andy Warhol's painting of a can of
Campbell's tomato soup. I say, 'This is art.'..." (Wagner,1986, p.
29).
Examine some potential defining characteristics. "A work of art is
a symbol for or a representation of reality". That does not seem
to include nonrepresentational art such as much of music and a
large category of visual art. Try another, "A work of art is
something that expresses some cultural truth". Heard a good
lecture lately ? Lots of things may contain cultural truths, but
not win universal agreement as works of art. In addition,
particularly with nonrepresentational art, there may be no clear
cultural message in items that
still are generally regarded as art.
The behavior and the personal characteristics of the artist are
often used to include objects in the category art. In its most
simplified form, this perspective defines a work of art as that
thing which is produced by an artist. In more disguised form, the
work is that which is purposively produced by a creative person.
In either case, the difficulty of definition is simply moved from
the object to the person, i.e., the problem now is defining the
concept artist. There is also a danger of circularity here, i.e.,
a work of art is what artists do, artists are those who do works of
art. So, to start somewhere, we will investigate what attributes exist in
visual art works that are generally
well-regarded.
Measurement of Aesthetic Responses
Aesthetic responses typically have been measured by (a) verbal
ratings or descriptions, (b) acquisitive behavior, (c) motoric
responses and (d) psychobiological reactions. Each of these will be
considered in detail.
Verbal Ratings or Descriptions.
This is probably the most commonly-used category of measurement
methods. Within the category, the most common procedure is the
rating scale, in which the observer is asked to assign to a
stimulus a number which places the stimulus at a point on some
dimension. For example, a dimension may be defined as ranging from
very good to very bad, with the number 1 corresponding to very good
and 7 to very bad. The observer then assigns a number between 1
and 7 to describe her evaluation of the stimulus. This approach
was championed by Berlyne (1974) and has also been used extensively
by Martindale (1991). It yields data which, depending upon the
particular polar adjective pairs and their number, can contain a
great deal of information about stimuli. These techniques have
also been used to judge the degree of similarity between and among
paintings. An additional benefit of these approaches is that the
data lend themselves to sophisticated statistical treatments, e.g.,
factor analysis and multidimensional
scaling.
A variant of the rating scale is the magnitude estimation technique
(c.f. Stevens, 1961). Here the subject is not limited to a
particular scale, but can use any number he wishes, although often
the experimenter will provide an anchor value. For example, the
observer might be instructed "If the goodness of this stimulus is
100, what is the goodness of that stimulus ?" This technique has
been used with great success in studies of perception because the
data it provides indicate that observers are using ratio
comparisons, which is more sophisticated than the rating scales
demand. However, these scales have not been employed in the study
of aesthetic responses. I think that investigators mistrust the
unrestrained nature of the response when they are studying both
stimuli and responses that are themselves likely to be
multidimensional.
Another common verbal measurement technique is the forced-choice
response. Often used to denote preference, the observer is asked
to pick between two stimuli the one she prefers. Of course, one
could ask the observer to choose on other criteria instead. While
this technique does not obtain much information on a single trial,
it can be quite sensitive to subtle differences if sufficient
numbers of trials and subjects
are employed (e.g., Levy, 1976).
Located somewhere between rating scales and forced-choice
procedures for the information produced on a single trial are
ranking judgments. This is an expanded forced-choice technique in
which the subject is provided more than two stimuli and is asked to
rank them, or order them, on some dimension. The specific ordering
patterns can be used to infer the criteria that observers use
(e.g., Cupchik and Gebotys, 1987), as well as provide some
quantitative estimate such as
mean rank for a stimulus.
Finally, some investigators have used discursive essay responses
from observers to attempt measurement of complex activities such as
strategic approaches to understanding a painting. Such essays can
be subjected to analyses such as the protocol analyses used in the
study of problem solving ( e.g., Newell and Simon,1972) to infer
the intellectual steps an observer may be taking in solving a
painting (e.g., Schmidt, McLaughlin
and Leighten, 1988).
It is important to realize that this has not been an exhaustive
list. There may be many ways to ask a subject what he is thinking
and then quantify the response, but these are general methods you
are likely to encounter.
Acquisition Behavior
A number of investigators, but Daniel Berlyne (1974) in particular,
have sought to measure aesthetic responses with other, more
indirect methods. Thus, a subject might be told to look at
paintings one-by-one, for as long as she likes. The amount of time
spent on each picture then provides a measure of the subject's
interest in the stimulus. Another approach is to ask a subject to
divide some amount of money into portions to "purchase" various
paintings, thus generating a relative preference rating. I am not
talking here about "investment" buying based on a painter's
identity, but only of laboratory
techniques.
Motoric Behavior
While subjects inspect paintings, many investigators have measured
their eye movements. The patterns of fixations across the picture
yields information about the areas to which the subject pays
attention and the sequence in which he attends (e.g., Molnar,
1981). Another measure of visual attention is the speed with which
a subject notices the presence or absence of some characteristic in
a stimulus, but this has not been used very often in the study of
aesthetics.
Psychophysiological Measures
Largely inspired by the work of Berlyne (1971;1974), investigators
have used the galvanic skin response (GSR) as an index of arousal
and, by extension, of emotional response. While this is another
valuable nonverbal technique, its inherent variability has limited
its use.
Early Developments in Psychological
Investigation.
Gustav Fechner launched the first experimental work on aesthetic
responses (Berlyne, 1971; Bornstein, 1984), testing the
attractiveness of the legendary golden ratio. The golden ratio
obtains when, for rectangle ABCD, AB/BC = BC/(AB+BC). From the
time of Pythagoras, claims have been made that shapes or segments
which contain this particular mathematical ratio are intrinsically
beautiful. Many observations have been made that the ratio is
found in nature, e.g., in the shapes of some leaves and in the
spiral of the Nautilis shell. Over the centuries, some painters,
e.g., Claude Lorrain, Piet Mondrian, have consciously used the
ratio in their compositions, while others, e.g., Leonardo Da Vinci,
Georges Seurat, seem to have employed it without being explicit
about it. It was Fechner, however, who offered the first empirical
evidence that observers actually did find the golden ratio more
pleasing than any other.
In 1865, he reported investigations of aesthetic responses to
rectangles that differed in the proportions of the lengths of their
sides, showing that the most preferred proportion was 1:1.62, the
famous golden ratio. The issue he studied, his methodological
approach and his findings are each illustrative of the
contributions that the science
has sought to make.
How did Fechner obtain his data ? In 1860, he had published his
Elements of Psychophysics, which included many detailed procedures
for varying physical energy and collecting judgments of the
resulting perceptual changes. Later, in 1865, he introduced the
method of choice, in which observers picked from a large set those
stimuli that possessed some characteristic most and least. In the
work on the golden ratio, subjects were asked to choose rectangles
they liked best and least. Averaging across the choices of many
subjects, he found that the "golden" rectangle was picked as most
preferred more often than any other and never picked as least
preferred (Bornstein, 1984; Woodworth, 1938). Preference was thus
described quantitatively as the probability of being chosen most or
least.
Why was this important ? The basic question here, of course, was
whether there are patterns that are universally appealing. If that
were so, the likely explanation would have to be sought more in the
nature of the biological system and less in some cultural
convention. Human biology is much more likely to be the same the
world over than is any cultural feature. While Fechner's data did
not answer the question of universality, the investigation of this
vaunted ratio brought the ubiquitous nature - nurture debate into
the field of aesthetics. To what extent are an individual's
aesthetic responses the results of a lifetime of experience with a
particular culture ? To what extent are those responses the
results of the particular and peculiar characteristics of the human
central nervous system ? This statement of the general problem is
a convenient framework for organizing much of the extant
psychological research on aesthetics.
Sigmund Freud was, obviously, another major figure in the history
of Psychology. He also had a great influence on the field of
aesthetics, applying his theories of motivation and of personality
development to the interpretation of particular art works and to a
theory of creativity.
As students of Psychology well know, the essential claim of Freud's
theories was that human biology provides the wellspring of human
motivation and that those motives are in constant conflict with the
restraining forces of culture and of physical reality. The
individual adult's personality is the result of all of the
successful and unsuccessful resolutions of those conflicts,
especially those encountered in the childhood years. Freud's
further claim here was that the adult's behavior patterns can be
interpreted with information about these conflicts, particularly
those that were unsuccessfully
resolved.
From this perspective, a parallel examination of the biography and
the work of a particular artist would yield information about the
artist's motivation for designing and composing a painting in the
specific way he did. Freud published such studies of works by
Leonardo da Vinci and by Michelangelo, trying to show a connection
between the content of a particular painting and some difficult
childhood events. As case-studies, these are interesting attempts,
but are impossible to confirm independently. Nevertheless, this
method has influenced many art historians and critics and also
inspired the field of Psychohistory, e.g., Erik Erikson's work on
Martin Luther (1958).
As I indicated, Freud also believed that his general theory offered
insight into the nature of creativity. Since the direct expression
of sexual energy is often thwarted, the omnipresent energy must be
redirected. This can be done, in Freud's view, in a relatively
healthy way by sublimation, in which the energy is channeled into
an adequate substitute activity. Creative activity is one such
substitute. In addition, he believed that the innovative and
original features of creativity were the result of the unusual,
even bizarre, associations in the thought patterns that
characterized the unconscious portions of mind. The creative
person, then, is one who is in closer touch with her unconscious
mind than the average person.
These were the beginnings of two traditions in Psychology and in
the psychological study of aesthetics. Since each was based on
data, experimentally or clinically derived, they are viewed as
examples of "aesthetics-from-below"
(Bornstein, 1984).